A Treatise of Human Nature

Front Cover
Clarendon Press, 1975 - Philosophy - 709 pages
Brickhouse and Smith argue, contrary to many modern interpretations of Plato's Apology of Socrates, that Plato's Socrates offers a sincere defence against the charges he faces. In doing so the book offers an exhaustive historical and philosophical interpretation of and commentary on Plato's Apology.

Contents

PART II
26
Of the other qualities of our ideas of space and time
33
Objections answerd
47
The same subject continud
53
Of the idea of existence and of external existence
66
Of probability and of the idea of cause and effect
73
Why a cause is always necessary?
78
Of the causes of belief
98
Difficulties solvd
347
Of our esteem for the rich and powerful
357
Of benevolence and anger
366
Of the amorous passion or love betwixt the sexes
394
The same subject continud
409
Of the causes of the violent passions
418
Of contiguity and distance in space and time
427
Of the direct passions
438

Of the effects of other relations and other habits
106
Of the probability of chances
124
Of the probability of causes
130
Of unphilosophical probability
143
Of the idea of necessary connexion
155
Rules by which to judge of causes and effects
173
PART IV
180
Of scepticism with regard to the senses
187
Of the antient philosophy
219
Of the modern philosophy
225
Of the immateriality of the soul
232
Of personal identity
251
Conclusion of this book
263
BOOK II
274
Of beauty and deformity
276
PART II
329
Of curiosity or the love of truth
448
OF MORALS
455
Moral distinctions derivd from a moral sense
470
PART II
477
Of the origin of justice and property
484
Of the rules that determine property
514
Of the origin of government
534
Of chastity and modesty
570
82
647
477
653
187
658
Of pride and humility their objects and causes
668
88888
672
Of goodness and benevolence
683
Of the influence of these relations on pride and humility
690
Some farther reflections concerning the natural virtues
705

Other editions - View all

About the author (1975)

David Hume was born in Edinburgh to a minor Scottish noble family, raised at the estate of Ninewells, and attended the University of Edinburgh for two years until he was 15. Although his family wished him to study law, he found himself unsuited to this. He studied at home, tried business briefly, and after receiving a small inheritance traveled to France, settling at La Fleche, where Descartes had gone to school. There he completed his first and major philosophical work, A Treatise of Human Nature (1739--40), published in three volumes. Hume claimed on the title page that he was introducing the experimental method of reasoning into moral subjects, and further that he was offering a new way of seeing the limits of human knowledge. Although his work was largely ignored, Hume gained from it a reputation as a philosophical skeptic and an opponent of traditional religion. (In later years he was called "the great infidel.") This reputation led to his being rejected for professorships at both Edinburgh and Glasgow. To earn his living he served variously as the secretary to General St. Clair, as the attendant to the mad Marquis of Annandale, and as the keeper of the Advocates Library in Edinburgh. While holding these positions, he wrote and published a new version of his philosophy, the two Enquiries, and many essays on social, political, moral, and literary subjects. He also began his six-volume History of England from the Roman Invasion to the Glorious Revolution (1754--62), the work that made him most famous in his lifetime. Hume retired from public life and settled in Edinburgh, where he was the leading figure in Scottish letters and a good friend to many of the leading intellectuals of the time, including Adam Smith and Benjamin Franklin. During this period, he completed the Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, which he had been working on for more than 25 years. Hume first worked on the Dialogues in the middle of his career, but put them aside as too provocative. In his last years he finished them and they were published posthumously in 1779. They are probably his best literary effort and have been the basis for continuous discussion and debate among philosophers of religion. Toward the end of Hume's life, his philosophical work began to be taken seriously, and the skeptical problems he had raised were tackled by philosophers in Scotland, France, and finally Germany, where Kant claimed that Hume had awakened him from his dogmatic slumbers. Hume was one of the most influential philosophers of modern times, both as a positive force on skeptical and empirical thinkers and as a philosopher to be refuted by others. Interpreters are still arguing about whether he should be seen as a complete skeptic, a partial skeptic, a precursor of logical positivism, or even a secret believer.

Bibliographic information